|
Taras VoznyakNotes on the Nature of Artistic ActsThere
are countless answers if one asks what the purpose of human artistic activities
is and what art itself is. And all of them are correct in some way. They are as
relevant within a certain range of what we call “reality” as the laws of Sir
Isaac Newton (1643–1727), even though a new physics, described by Albert
Einstein (1879–1955) in his theory of relativity, was formulated a hundred
years ago. At the same time, it must be noted that all these answers address
partial cases. Or they pertain not to a comprehensive understanding of artistic
activities (and we will later see that this involves activities in their
broadest, most all-encompassing sense) but to specific spheres of human
activities that are distinguished as particular “artistic” domains, as if
artistic acts are carried out only in relation to these specific domains and
not concerning other spheres of human activities. This, of course, is a very
artificial division. It was once believed that artistic acts could only relate
to the “beautiful” or “beauty” and that the abhorrent and drastic were not part
of artistic acts. Of course, this narrows the essence of creative acts, which
indeed encompass artistic acts. Therefore, we must clarify that we are not
discussing “fine arts” (French: Les beaux-arts, German: feine
Künste or schöne Künste), nor mere craftsmanship or applied arts, but
rather the creativity of a person in shaping the environment around them, an
individual’s creativity in shaping the world. We will focus on creative
practices that I would term “artistic”, as they require a particular skill,
craftsmanship, and artistry but extend far beyond traditional notions of the
“fine arts”. So, the definitions of conventional “artistic” subjects are
irrelevant here; they are only partial aspects. And what interests us is
exploring the broadest understanding of creative (or “artistic”, as I
understand it) practices. However,
even by radically expanding the sphere to which human creative or artistic activities
relate, we can see that we are dealing with three different definitions of the
nature of “artistic” practices. It
appears that they are seemingly unrelated to each other. Moreover, they
contradict each other. The
first, most simple definition within this already expanded interpretation of
the artistic practices’ nature is that the artistic act should “reflect” the
world (mimetic function – from the Greek μίμησις
– imitation, μιμεῖσθαι
“to imitate”). But to “reflect” the world, it must undergo a certain process
because it doesn’t “reveal” things but phenomena. A person “gathers” and
“constructs” “things” from them, and then, as their sum, the entire
comprehensive “world” in which we live. And thus, this “artistic” practice, in
a specific sense of the word, “presents” the person’s own “world” to them.
However, in doing so, the person works with phenomena that are already present
to them in this world through senses (such as things), feelings (such as
states), and even through intellectual efforts (such as mathematical entities).
One does not go beyond the present, beyond the continuum of what has appeared
to them and, accordingly, became accessible. The sum of the world “gathered”
and “reflected” in this way is limited, confined within its continuum, and only
reduces to this present realm. Therefore, this interpretation of artistic
practices reduces solely to “gathering the world” and “reflecting the world”.
At the same time, the first definition of artistic practices’ nature does not
complete or build the world further; it only “gathers” and “reflects” it.
Despite their apparent “creative” nature, artistic practices of the first type
operate within a limited continuum of the existing, already present phenomena.
Their sole function is to “gather things and the world”, giving it the familiar
appearance of a collection of things, a locked continuum of entities. The
second view within this already expanded interpretation of the artistic
practices’ nature is that the artistic act is the tool or process that, unlike
the first type of artistic practices, “discloses”, “completes”, and “develops”
the world. Through artistic practices of the second type, the world breaks out
from the continuum of presences into the non-present, into that which is beyond
the world as a continuum of being. These second-type practices are much more
elusive and mysterious than the first-type. Artistic practices of the second
type “draw” new existences from the non-being, the non-apparent, the
world-transcendent, and “place” them before us; that is, they “place” them into
the world. They work with the non-present rather than the present, unlike
artistic practices of the first type. Through artistic practices of the second
type, the world as we know it is enlarged and expanded. What enables this
transition from the non-apparent to the apparent, and hence into essence, is
something mysterious and elusive that accompanies all that is present, namely
the existence, which is delineated by the term “being”. However, it is not
possible to fully delineate it. Yet, desperate efforts are made. But for our
purposes in this discussion, this remark will suffice. The
third definition within this expanded interpretation of the artistic practices’
nature pertains specifically to relationships with the “being”. Therefore, the
third definition entails that the artistic act does not merely aim to “reflect”
things or the world or to “draw out” these things into the world to “place”
them before us, thereby creating that world. Instead, it performs a truly mysterious
function – it preserves the connection with the mysterious “being”, reaching
the existential essence of the world, the very foundation of its existence. The
third type of artistic practice imposes and maintains the world’s connection
with its fundamental essence, the being. “If we say that entities ‘have
meaning’, this signifies that they have become accessible in their Being; and
this Being, as projected upon its ‘upon-which’, is what ‘really’ ‘has meaning’
first of all. Entities ‘have’ meaning only because, as Being which has been
disclosed beforehand, they become intelligible in the projection of that
Being…” [1; 373]. Artistic practices of the third type restore the primary and
often unconscious or lost sense of the world, which lies in its connection with
its existential foundation. Thus, the interpreted artistic practices restore
the existential, meaning-giving essence of things and the world and restore and
preserve the existential foundation within the human being itself. This third
type of practice overcomes the alienation of human beings from the existential
foundation of the world, and themselves embodied within it. Therefore, the
third type of practice restores the “human authenticity” to the person, the
authenticity of their dwelling, being-in-the-world, and being-with-the-world. Which
of these practices should we prefer? One that merely reflects the presence? The
reflective one? One that “heals” the world into a certain, albeit closed,
unity? Or
perhaps the practice that expands the world, probing the spaces of the
non-apparent and “drawing” new phenomena into existence? Or maybe the one that
returns to the world and, simultaneously, to a person, their connection to
existence? As
we can see, all these definitions relate to the human being, the world, and how
it relates to the human, as well as the relation of a human and the world to
existence. Therefore,
all three definitions of artistic practices complement each other rather than
contradict each other, and they make sense. We
will lose ourselves if we lose the profound connection with the existential
foundation of the world, which artistic practices of the third type prevent,
helping us to maintain or restore this connection. We
live not in a closed, limited-by-presence world that does not expand and
remains frozen in its continuum but in a living and dynamic world (and here it
is worth mentioning in passing the well-known physical, not philosophical,
theory of “expanding universe” in a completely unexpected, philosophical sense
of the word). Artistic practices of the second type, rightfully called
creative, assist individuals in constructing their abode, the world in which
they are embodied. We
would live in a world of illusions, fata morganas, where appearances are
unbound to anything, if we did not “gather” them into wholeness, into things,
into the world, and thus into ourselves within it. With the help of the
first-typed practices, we gather these phenomena into a solid foundation called
“the world”. Therefore, artistic practices of the first type delineate this
process of “gathering” the world, giving it a “material” form, endowing it with
“reality”, but not in the traditional, simplified sense of the word. So,
we have three separate definitions of the essence and tasks or functions of
artistic acts. And it seems that these three types of acts are not connected in
any way. Moreover, they lead to different definitions of the nature of art as a
particular kind of human activity. Is it so? Perhaps these different types of
artistic acts relate to different spheres of the emergence of what we
simplistically call “the world”? In reality, it seems that the functioning of
these three types of artistic activities relates to different levels of the
functioning of the “world” itself. Therefore,
we cannot avoid combining these three practices, which, as we see, have
profound meaning in the relationships between a person, the world, and
existence. Let
us start with the first definition: like every act of observation and
experience through distinct phenomena, the artistic act uniquely brings them
together into “wholeness”. We then call it either “thing” (when referring to a
limited circle of clearly related phenomena) or “world” (when referring to all
accessible phenomena that have come together as “things”). By
“things” I mean not only “objects” in our usual everyday sense, such as stones
or lamps. I also refer to entities that can be considered ideal: ideas,
abstract concepts like numbers, relationships between ideas and numbers
(objects of logic, thought, or mathematics), philosophical categories, and
subjects of philosophical inquiry in general, and so on. They, too, are, in the
broadest sense of the word, “things” that, in a specific manner (which we will
discuss later), “enter into” essence, become “present”, and collectively
“create” our world. When I expanded the concept of “things”, I referred to an
attempt by the founder of phenomenology as a philosophical direction, Edmund
Husserl (1859–1938), to rely precisely on these seemingly ideal essences in the
quest for a solid foundation in the world of such uncertain and ephemeral
phenomena – “<...> Moreover, this world is there for me not only as a
world of mere things, but also with the same immediacy as a world of objects with values, a world of goods, a practical world.
I simply find the physical things in front of me furnished not only with merely
material determinations but also with value-characteristics, as beautiful and
ugly, pleasant and unpleasant, agreeable and disagreeable, and the like.
Immediately, physical things stand there as Objects of use, the ‘table’ with
its ‘books’, the ‘drinking glass’, the ‘vase’, the ‘piano’, etc. These
value-characteristics and practical characteristics also belong constitutively to the Objects ‘on hand’ as
Objects, regardless of whether or not I turn to such characteristics and
the Objects. Naturally this applies not only in the case of the ‘mere physical
things’, but also in the case of humans and brute animals belonging to my
surroundings. They are my ‘friends’ or ‘enemies’, my ‘servants’ or ‘superiors’,
‘strangers’ or ‘relatives’, etc.” [2; 53]. However,
the “world” is not a limited number of “things” and processes that eternally
repeats its vast cycles, as in Nietzsche (Friedrich Nietzsche, 1844–1900). It
is open-ended – new “things” emerge; thus, the world grows, accrues, expands,
and diversifies. This “disclosure” is accomplished through the second of the
activities we have delineated, which are artistic in their essence. These are
acts of “drawing” new presences, new “things”, new “realities” from the
non-present, from non-being, as we have come to call these presences. An
insightful reader will immediately recognise or suspect simple acts of
cognition here. And they will be both right and not entirely right. They will
be wrong because cognition, in our usual understanding, “comprehends” a priori
existing “things” and “realities”, about which there is no doubt that they
“exist” and are present. This is precisely what Husserl writes about, although
he conditions the infinite spatial, temporal, and substantial variability of
the thing, yet the same thing, which is unified in all its manifestations by
one “idea” of the same thing. Then, this “cognition” is reduced to the first
form of artistic activities, when the artistic act consolidates a group of
existing phenomena into a specific “thing”, creating a “whole” from them,
strictly following Husserl’s phenomenological approach. In
contrast, the second type of activities, which we can call “creative”, are
artistic acts of “drawing into existence” the non-present absences, not
“essences”, but “absences”, “non-presences”. The second-type acts probe the
spaces or spheres of the absence to “pull from them into essence”, to make
“existent”, in the simplest and most obvious sense of the word “present”,
something that previously did not exist. These acts make something present from
the absence of something (if such a phrase can be used), making the absent
“something” present and existing. And thereby, they create the world from the
sum of these existing “somethings”. Artistic acts of the second type “place”
absences in the world of existence, drawing phenomena from their absence into
presence, before-us-being, into before-presence. After
that, artistic acts of the first type weld these phenomena, drawn into
confrontation, into certain “wholes”, which we call “things”, and the
all-encompassing wholeness of things, which we, of course, call the “world”. However,
this “drawing in” of the un-present into the present occurs as an involvement,
which makes this un-present “existent”. And what makes the non-present present
as a phenomenon is the being. The imposition of a connection with the being
constitutes the essence of the third-typed acts. In these acts, the artist
addresses the fundamental basis of all that exists – the world. And with this
appeal, the artist maintains the connection of the existent with its basis –
the being. But “<...> for us Being is only an empty word with an
evanescent meaning – then we deposed it and thus demoted it from its authentic
rank. In contrast, for our Dasein, this – that we understand Being, if only in
an indefinite way – has the highest rank, insofar as in this, a power announces
itself in which the very possibility of the essence of our Dasein is grounded…
Yet even in order for Dasein to remain an indifferent being for us, we must
understand Being” [3; 90]. In this way, the world maintains its connection with
its existential basis and, therefore, sustains its constancy, in the complete
sense of the word, its solidity while simultaneously sustaining the grounds for
development, unfolding, and expanding. Solidity is based on the inseparability
of the being with its origin – the being. The existent flows from the being.
The existence is sustained by the being as long as it maintains an inseparable
connection with it. Therefore, I would even venture to propose such a formula –
the existent exists in being around/under/behind the being. The existent cannot
exist outside the connection with the being. Thus, the artistic acts of the
third type provide this connection between the being and the present. As
we can see, all these seemingly different functions and definitions of forms of
artistic activities/acts are not so unrelated to each other. In reality, they are
parts of the same process of creating/becoming/emerging of the world, the
emergence of the un-being into the being, followed by the healing of these
disparate existences/phenomena into “wholes”, “things”, and ultimately, into
the “world”. Although, if we do not delve into the deep mechanisms of this
process, it can be interpreted as a simple “cognition” of the world, which we
have discussed previously. In reality, we are dealing with a significant,
multi-level process of making and creating the world, not a simple act of
comprehending it. And that is why I call these activities precisely artistic
activities. Therefore,
artistic acts are far from merely the creation of paintings or literary texts.
Artistic activities, in the broadest sense of the word, are the creation of the
world. And this is how the great predecessors saw them. If, by artistic
activities, we only understand the creation of paintings, literary texts, or
even interiors, then we are talking about craftsmanship and mastery of that
craft. Instead, I would see in artistic acts their primordial basis, namely,
creativity in the metaphysical, supra-essential sense of the word. And in this
sense, art creates the world – no more or less. But then, all these three forms
of artistic activity (and, accordingly, three definitions of the nature of
artistic acts) are merely outlines of three stages of this world creation. And
then, obviously, we should begin describing this creation of the existent or
the world in reverse order, starting from the being and ending with the
existent, which artistic acts “place” before us as the “world”. Thus,
an artistic act of the third type appeals to the being and maintains an
inseparable connection with the being. Based on this appeal and connection with
the being, an artistic act of the second type “draws into existence” the things
which did not exist before and “draws” non-presences into presence. And in the
world of the present, these non-presences become manifested phenomena. However,
at that moment, they are not being “entities” in the specific sense of the
word. The next creative act makes them “entities” – an artistic act of the
first type, which makes a whole of the already manifested phenomena we
designate as “things”. And then the same artistic activity of the first type
“unites” these disparate “things” into what we then call the “world”. Thus,
all these three definitions of the nature of the artistic act describe, at
different stages, the same, indeed indivisible process, not so much of
cognition, as it seems, but of the creation of the world. The
only question that remains is – who is the protagonist of this creation of the
world – because we are dealing both with the artist, more precisely the human
in the broadest sense of the word, and with the being. So, what is the source
of the world – the artist, that is, the human or the being? Hence,
we face the following puzzle. We described this creation process in such a way
that it may seem that the main promoter of it is the artist, that is, the
human. However, as we can see, the being does not depend on the human, so this
is not entirely true. The being, the manifestation of phenomena (that has
manifested itself), the very self-evidence, and the essence (that which already
“is”) are not entirely dependent on the will of the subject, the artist, or the
person, although they require their presence. Although without the human, the
artist, this process of world creation, its
becoming, is impossible without just the human in the broadest sense of the
word. And in this sense, we are all artists. However, the human, the artist,
only has the chance to send a request towards the being – or nothingness, if
viewed from the side of the existent world. And the human, the artist, receives
an answer from the being in the form of scattered phenomena. Then more depends
on the human. They unite part of these scatterings into a specific “thing”.
Then, they mount this “thing” into a combination of all the known things humans
have made a whole. This combination is called the “world”. Thus, the person,
the artist, constructs their world. However,
what we define as either the being or nothingness remains a mystery, from which
phenomena emerge, and then things, and ultimately, the world. Therefore, there
is no basis for human or artistic pride because we become “creators” thanks to
the mystery of our connection with the being. But the great calling and
function of the person, the artist, is to maintain this essential connection –
for both humanity and the world – with the being or nothingness, for it is
thanks to this connection that the human exists and the world emerges. My
interpretation of art goes far beyond the traditional interpretation of its
nature by art history disciplines. They narrowly interpret it as the skill of
representation – whether of things or the world as a whole. So, most canonical
interpretations of art focus mainly on its mimetic function. They don't even
notice that they are talking about craftsmanship, about skill. In
contrast, I see art as an inventive, world-creating act that encompasses not
only the representation of the existent in certain secondary images but also
the very act of contemplation and gathering of phenomena into wholes, binding
these wholes into an all-encompassing whole, which we call the “world”, and most
importantly, the primary function of art is to protect the connection of both
humanity and the world with the being – its fundamental essence. Nonetheless,
art in the narrow sense of the word, as understood by art history disciplines,
also falls under my expanded interpretation. Therefore,
it might be interesting to illustrate all these three types of artistic
activities with concrete examples. Artistic
activity of the first type I would illustrate with the work of artists who
“gather” things and the world. Foremost among them are artists from Ancient
Greece. The preserved sculptures of Phidias (Φειδίας,
c. 490–430 BC), Praxiteles (Πραξιτέλης,
c. 400 – after 340–320 BC), Polykleitos (Πολύκλειτος,
489–419 BC), Myron (Μύρων,
5th century BC), Scopas (Σκόπας,
395–350 BC), Lysippos (Λύσιππος,
390–300 BC). They “gathered” the known world of classical Ancient Greece for
us, laying the foundations of our European world. The world of the ancient
Greeks emerged as a wholeness, as a whole world. Similarly,
almost all Renaissance artists can be included, who, after centuries of
decline, “constructed” the visualisation of our world. Not only that, but in
addition to visual art, there is also architecture, which “furnishes” our
inhabited world. Among the Renaissance artists are Leonardo da Vinci (Leonardo
di ser Piero da Vinci, 1452–1519), Michelangelo Buonarroti (Michelangelo di
Lodovico di Leonardo di Buonarroti Simoni, 1475–1564), Raphael Santi (Raffaello Santi, Raffaello Sanzio, 1483–1520), Donatello (Donatello, Donato di
Niccolò di Betto Bardi,
1386–1466), Sandro Botticelli (Alessandro di Mariano di Vanni
Filipepi, 1445–1510), and others. Their creative
method consisted precisely of “gathering” things and the world – an incredible
act that shaped our European world and was “constructed” as a harmonious whole. Surprisingly,
artists classified as the first type of actors can be named traditionalists.
However, they are traditionalists in creating great world-building traditions
since the ancient Greek world and the world of Renaissance creators, in a
certain sense, exist to this day. They made these worlds and traditions, and
thanks to their artistic acts, the world they created retains the same general
outlines. In this sense, they could even be called the conservatives of our
world. In
the same way, Paul Cézanne (1839–1906) was a “collector” of things and
the world after the destruction by the Impressionists. He returned the world’s
“materiality”, “grounded” it, “pulled” it from the Impressionist mirages, and
essentially, returned it to humanity. In this sense, he is not only the father
of Post-Impressionism but also a neoconservative and neotraditionalist,
albeit on a different level than the naive “realists” of previous eras. Surprisingly,
another such “collector” of the world was Pablo Picasso (1881–1973) during his
Synthetic Cubist period. Then, he was “collecting” the mirror of the world that
he “shattered” during his Analytical (or rather, destructive) Cubist period. He
continued the trajectory of artistic activities proposed by Paul Cézanne
(referring to Picasso’s first “Cézannean”
period of Cubist explorations). Henri
Matisse (1869–1954) can also be included among these “collectors” of the world.
He “collected” this world after the tumultuous period of its destruction by the
Impressionists in their ultimate intentions, such as the luxurious but
dangerous destructor Claude Monet (1840–1926), who hid in the lush gardens of
Giverny. In
literature, we have an excellent example of such traditionalists – our Neoclassicists – Mykola Zerov (1890–1937), Maksym Rylskyi
(1895–1964), Oswald Burghardt (1891–1947), and Mykhailo
Drai-Khmara (1889–1939). In
Ukrainian visual art, Mykhailo Boichuk
(1882–1937) and the school of “Boichukists”
desperately tried to return our Ukrainian world to its East European
Neo-Byzantine classics and Proto-Renaissance. Not only in iconography, as some
might think today, but in life – he painted frescoes in barracks, theatres,
sanatoriums, and institutes. Thus, he collected the Ukrainian world as he understood
it. Centuries have passed, and Boichuk attempted to
repeat in contemporary realities the act carried out by the artists of the
Renaissance era. In
modern Ukraine, among young artists, I would include Olena
Pryduvalova (1960) in this constructive artistic
movement. I mention her because I am somewhat familiar with her oeuvre. From
the fragments and debris of the world, Pryduvalova
repeatedly gathers it together, giving us a chance and an opportunity again and
again. The
second type of artistic activity, I would illustrate with the works of artists
who “pull” entirely new things into the world and existence. These are
“revolutionaries” and “avant-gardists” in the proper sense of the word. It is
impossible to list all these avant-garde movements and trends. But again, we
must first mention Pablo Picasso because he was not just one artist but a good
dozen different artists. His Analytical Cubist period did not deconstruct
things so much as it pulled the elements and phenomena from which they were
composed into the world. Most
spectacularly, if not scandalously, Salvador Dalí (1904–1989) tried to
“draw” new realities from the non-present into the present. Surrealism was
perhaps the most desperate attempt to “draw” things into the world that were
not there before. And here, it is difficult not to mention René Magritte
(1898–1967) and Giorgio de Chirico (1888–1978). In literature, André
Breton (1896–1966) and Antonin Artaud (1896–1948). James
Joyce (1882–1941) with his “Ulysses” (1922) and finally “Finnegans
Wake” (1939), and Samuel Beckett (1906–1989) with his novels “Molloy” (1951),
“Malone Dies” (1951), and “The Unnamable” (1953) also
“explored” regions of the non-existent and built upon our European worlds. Of
course, in this list of artists, one cannot ignore Francis Bacon (1909–1992),
who visualised the probes into the non-existent of his Irish companions and
eternal exiles, Joyce and Beckett. Among
the classics of Ukrainian art, one cannot fail to mention such explorers of the
regions of the non-existent as the avant-gardist, suprematist,
and later founder of non-objective art (which is another story) Kazymyr Malevych (1879–1935), the
world's first abstractionist Vasyl Kandynskyi (1866–1944), futurist Davyd
Burliuk (1882–1967), avant-gardist Vasyl Yermylov (1894–1968), cubo-futurist and later spectralist
Oleksandr Bohomazov (1880–1930), cubist and futurist Oleksandra Ekster (1882–1949),
founder of Constructivism Volodymyr Tatlin
(1885–1953), avant-gardist Klyment Redko (1897–1956) and many others. And
the idol of Cubist sculpture Oleksandr Arkhypenko
(1887–1964), who, from absent forms, voids, “extracted” their presence, their
materiality. Returning
to contemporary Ukrainian contexts, the most spectacular artist who, with
incredible courage, “probes” the regions of the non-existent is Vlada Ralko (1969). Not only does
she show the suffering from the war that has been ongoing for two decades, but
she also, in her way, points to the metaphysical causes of this existential
war. And they are beyond the obvious. As
for the artists who establish and maintain our connection with the being, that
is the third type of artists, some incredible flamboyance does not distinguish
them; they are rather “quiet” and “focused” but immensely deep. Being “shines”
from their canvases, as in the works of Rembrandt (1606/1607–1669) or
Velázquez (1599–1660). Similarly, it streams from the canvases of
Caravaggio (1571–1610). Do they “depict” this elusive and mysterious being on
their canvases? Not at all. They point to its presence in an unobvious way.
They do not “show” the being, as this is impossible, but they “indicate” it in
their artistic way. Looking at the mysterious “Las Meninas” by
Velázquez, or the eyes of older people in Rembrandt’s portraits, or
genuinely human, not divine bodies in Caravaggio’s paintings, we can feel and
think about something. They “point” to something. So,
what are the portraits of royal dwarfs about? About the whims of the royal
court? About the perverse collecting of unfortunate cripples? Or about something
that lies beyond them... What about the portraits of degenerate kings? About
the majesty of the kings above kings, the Habsburgs? Or about something that
lies beyond them... And “Las Meninas”, what is it, a secular scene? A
self-portrait? A reflection in a reflection? Or is it about us and the world as
a reflection of the being? What does Velázquez “indicate”? Even
the inner light coming from the naked body of Rembrandt's young wife, Saskia,
is about the same. It's not about the beauty of a young woman. Not about the
somewhat posing, but we are not fooled – sad, questioning – bravado of her
still young husband, Rembrandt, but about something more essential that streams
from beyond her body, which for a brief moment of her youth allowed her to be
so radiant. In the portraits of older people, only fragments of this radiance
of the being and the fading sparks in their eyes remain. Everything else has
already lost its connection with this being and is again returning to
nothingness… With
incredible efforts of his talent, Caravaggio tore himself away from the
idealising refinement of Da Vinci or Raphael. He broke through to the
foundations of the existence of human bodies not through their Platonic
idealisation, depicting not the body as a body but its perfect idea (let’s
recall the desperate efforts in this direction of the modern “Platonist”
Husserl), the flesh of the existing body. He would not have succeeded without
the supportive and enabling being that makes it possible. And we intuitively
“understand” this or “see” it (here, let’s recall his apprentice, but also
opponent, Heidegger). Again,
Picasso, in his late philosophical graphic works, depicted the world of
classical Greece, full of philosopher-artists (and this is none other than the
maestro himself), goat-footed fauns, satyrs, and naked nymphs. There, he
ascended to the heights of direct connection with the being. At least he seemed
to ponder it. He indicated the elusive. So, as we see, in one artist, Picasso,
there were at least several completely different artists. But this required his
vital and artistic power. Therefore,
this rather conditional division cannot be absolutised.
All these three artistic activities intertwine and complement each other.
Similarly, artists, to the extent of their talent, resort to all three
techniques simultaneously, both “collecting” the world, “building” it, and
“preserving” our connection with the being. 1. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being
and Time. Translated by J. Macquarrie and E.
Robinson. Blackwell Publishers 2. Husserl, E. (1983). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and
to a phenomenological philosophy. First Book: General introduction to a pure phenomenology. Translated by F.
Kersten. Husserliana Collected Works Vol. II. Den
Haag: Nijhoff 3. Heidegger, M. (2014). Introduction to metaphysics. Second
edition. Translated by Gregory Fried and Richard Polt.
Yale University Press 12–20 June, 2024, Lviv-Krakow |